Joseph Fletcher

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Joseph Francis Fletcher
Born(1905-04-10)April 10, 1905
DiedOctober 28, 1991(1991-10-28) (aged 86)
NationalityAmerican
Alma materWest Virginia University, Berkeley Divinity School, Yale University, London School of Economics
Occupation(s)Theologian, Episcopal priest, educator, author
Employer(s)Episcopal Theological School, Harvard University, University of Virginia
Known forSituational ethics, biomedical ethics
AwardsHumanist of the Year

Joseph Francis Fletcher (April 10, 1905 in Newark, New Jersey - October 28, 1991 in Charlottesville, Virginia)[1] was an American professor who founded the theory of situational ethics in the 1960s, and was a pioneer in the field of bioethics. Fletcher was a leading academic proponent of the potential benefits of abortion, infanticide, euthanasia, eugenics, and cloning. Ordained as an Episcopal priest, he later identified himself as an atheist.[citation needed]

Life[edit]

Fletcher was a prolific academic, teaching, participating in symposia, and completing ten books, and hundreds of articles, book reviews, and translations. He taught Christian Ethics at Episcopal Divinity School, Cambridge, Massachusetts, and at Harvard Divinity School from 1944 to 1970. He was the first professor of medical ethics at the University of Virginia and co-founded the Program in Biology and Society there. He retired from teaching in 1977.

In 1974, the American Humanist Association named him Humanist of the Year. He was one of the signers of the Humanist Manifesto.[2]

He served as president of the Euthanasia Society of America (later renamed the Society for the Right to Die) from 1974 to 1976. He was also a member of the American Eugenics Society and the Association for Voluntary Sterilization.[citation needed]

One of his children, Joseph F. Fletcher Jr. was a historian.[citation needed]

Quotes[edit]

"We need to educate people to the idea that the quality of life is more important than mere length of life. Our cultural tradition holds that life has absolute value, but that is really not good enough anymore. Sometimes, no life is better."[citation needed]

“mercy killing” is justified for “an incorrigible ‘human vegetable,’ whether spontaneously functioning or artificially supported, [who] is progressively degraded while constantly eating up private or public financial resources in violation of the distributive justice owed to others.” Joseph Fletcher, “Ethics and Euthanasia,” in Horan and Mall, eds., Death, Dying, and Euthanasia, p. 301.

"Ethics critically examines values and how they are to be acted out; but whether they are acted out or not, loyalty to them depends on character or personal quality, and so it follows that the quality of medicine depends on the character of its clinicians."[citation needed]

"We ought to love people and use things; the essence of immorality is to love things and use people."

"People [with children with Down's syndrome]... have no reason to feel guilty about putting a Down's syndrome baby away, whether it's "put away" in the sense of hidden in a sanitarium or in a more responsible lethal sense. It is sad; yes. Dreadful. But it carries no guilt. True guilt arises only from an offense against a person, and a Down's is not a person."[3]

Notes[edit]

  1. ^ John R. Shook, Dictionary Of Modern American Philosophers, Vol. 1, Continuum International Publishing Group, 2005, p. 803
  2. ^ "Humanist Manifesto II". American Humanist Association. Archived from the original on October 20, 2012. Retrieved October 14, 2012.
  3. ^ Bard, Bernard; Joseph Fletcher (April 1968). "The Right to Die". The Atlantic Monthly: 59–64.

References[edit]

Notable works[edit]

  • 1954 Morals and Medicine N.J.: Princeton University Press.
  • 1966 Situation Ethics: The New Morality, Philadelphia: Westminster Press. (translated into 5 languages)
  • 1974 The Ethics of Genetic Control: Ending Reproductive Roulette. New York: Doubleday.

External links[edit]